Part III (Secunda Secundae) Part 79 (1/2)
Obj. 3: Further, the Philosopher says (Ethic. iv, 3) the ”magnanimous man is slow and leisurely.” Now slowness is contrary to solicitude.
Since then prudence is not opposed to magnanimity, for ”good is not opposed to good,” as stated in the _Predicaments_ (viii) it would seem that solicitude does not belong to prudence.
_On the contrary,_ It is written (1 Pet. 4:7): ”Be prudent ... and watch in prayers.” But watchfulness is the same as solicitude.
Therefore solicitude belongs to prudence.
_I answer that,_ According to Isidore (Etym. x), a man is said to be solicitous through being shrewd (_solers_) and alert (_citus_), in so far as a man through a certain shrewdness of mind is on the alert to do whatever has to be done. Now this belongs to prudence, whose chief act is a command about what has been already counselled and judged in matters of action. Hence the Philosopher says (Ethic. vi, 9) that ”one should be quick in carrying out the counsel taken, but slow in taking counsel.” Hence it is that solicitude belongs properly to prudence, and for this reason Augustine says (De Morib. Eccl. xxiv) that ”prudence keeps most careful watch and ward, lest by degrees we be deceived unawares by evil counsel.”
Reply Obj. 1: Movement belongs to the appet.i.tive power as to the principle of movement, in accordance however, with the direction and command of reason, wherein solicitude consists.
Reply Obj. 2: According to the Philosopher (Ethic. i, 3), ”equal certainty should not be sought in all things, but in each matter according to its proper mode.” And since the matter of prudence is the contingent singulars about which are human actions, the certainty of prudence cannot be so great as to be devoid of all solicitude.
Reply Obj. 3: The magnanimous man is said to be ”slow and leisurely”
not because he is solicitous about nothing, but because he is not over-solicitous about many things, and is trustful in matters where he ought to have trust, and is not over-solicitous about them: for over-much fear and distrust are the cause of over-solicitude, since fear makes us take counsel, as stated above (I-II, Q. 44, A. 2) when we were treating of the pa.s.sion of fear.
_______________________
TENTH ARTICLE [II-II, Q. 47, Art. 10]
Whether Solicitude Belongs to Prudence?
Objection 1: It would seem that prudence does not extend to the governing of many, but only to the government of oneself. For the Philosopher says (Ethic. v, 1) that virtue directed to the common good is justice. But prudence differs from justice. Therefore prudence is not directed to the common good.
Obj. 2: Further, he seems to be prudent, who seeks and does good for himself. Now those who seek the common good often neglect their own.
Therefore they are not prudent.
Obj. 3: Further, prudence is specifically distinct from temperance and fort.i.tude. But temperance and fort.i.tude seem to be related only to a man's own good. Therefore the same applies to prudence.
_On the contrary,_ Our Lord said (Matt. 24:45): ”Who, thinkest thou, is a faithful and prudent [Douay: 'wise'] servant whom his lord hath appointed over his family?”
_I answer that,_ According to the Philosopher (Ethic. vi, 8) some have held that prudence does not extend to the common good, but only to the good of the individual, and this because they thought that man is not bound to seek other than his own good. But this opinion is opposed to charity, which ”seeketh not her own” (1 Cor. 13:5): wherefore the Apostle says of himself (1 Cor. 10:33): ”Not seeking that which is profitable to myself, but to many, that they may be saved.” Moreover it is contrary to right reason, which judges the common good to be better than the good of the individual.
Accordingly, since it belongs to prudence rightly to counsel, judge, and command concerning the means of obtaining a due end, it is evident that prudence regards not only the private good of the individual, but also the common good of the mult.i.tude.
Reply Obj. 1: The Philosopher is speaking there of moral virtue. Now just as every moral virtue that is directed to the common good is called ”legal” justice, so the prudence that is directed to the common good is called ”political” prudence, for the latter stands in the same relation to legal justice, as prudence simply so called to moral virtue.
Reply Obj. 2: He that seeks the good of the many, seeks in consequence his own good, for two reasons. First, because the individual good is impossible without the common good of the family, state, or kingdom. Hence Valerius Maximus says [*Fact. et Dict.
Memor. iv, 6] of the ancient Romans that ”they would rather be poor in a rich empire than rich in a poor empire.” Secondly, because, since man is a part of the home and state, he must needs consider what is good for him by being prudent about the good of the many. For the good disposition of parts depends on their relation to the whole; thus Augustine says (Confess. iii, 8) that ”any part which does not harmonize with its whole, is offensive.”
Reply Obj. 3: Even temperance and fort.i.tude can be directed to the common good, hence there are precepts of law concerning them as stated in _Ethic._ v, 1: more so, however, prudence and justice, since these belong to the rational faculty which directly regards the universal, just as the sensitive part regards singulars.
_______________________
ELEVENTH ARTICLE [II-II, Q. 47, Art. 11]
Whether Prudence About One's Own Good Is Specifically the Same As That Which Extends to the Common Good?
Objection 1: It seems that prudence about one's own good is the same specifically as that which extends to the common good. For the Philosopher says (Ethic. vi, 8) that ”political prudence, and prudence are the same habit, yet their essence is not the same.”
Obj. 2: Further, the Philosopher says (Polit. iii, 2) that ”virtue is the same in a good man and in a good ruler.” Now political prudence is chiefly in the ruler, in whom it is architectonic, as it were.
Since then prudence is a virtue of a good man, it seems that prudence and political prudence are the same habit.